Discussion about this post

User's avatar
Robert Bristow-Johnson's avatar

Steven, I clearly agree with you that "The battle over democratic values manifests in the electoral system". And specifically, that "when you select an electoral system -- whether winner-take-all, proportional representation, instant runoffs, districts, at-large, cumulative voting or one of the other many methods available -- for your local, state or national elections, in a sense you are selecting a set of values and philosophy of government. Consequently, more than talking about studying the winner-take-all electoral system, it is more appropriate to talk about the winner-take-all political system."

Full agreement.

Now, I think that this means, conversely, is that the values that an electoral system is based on trickle down (or trickle up, whatever direction) into the political system.

I want a political system based on facts, *truth*, and on respecting the inherent equality of all persons subject to the system. That inherent equality means that we must have a participatory system - if schlubs like me cannot participate equally, cannot have a voice, I'm not really equal. But this also means that, to protect your equality, my voice does not systemically dominate over your voice. Now, with an elected official, most certainly their voice is more prominent, louder, than the voice of a schlub. But that's what representative democracy is about. I don't get to speak in the Vermont House of Representatives or the Vermont Senate, but the candidates elected from my district do.

For us schlubs, it's our vote that is our primary voice. Our access to meet with (lobby) our representatives is also there, but for most people, they will seldom or never be speaking with their representatives, but they're voting for (or against) them. That's their voice.

The equality of our vote is sacrosanct. Too many people have literally died in seeking or defending that equality. We must hold that equality of our vote (often expressed as "one-person-one-vote", but there are historical nuances to that term) *above* utilitarian values. Utilitarian values are important regarding the distribution of resources: taxation, welfare, aid/assistance. But in elections, utilitarianism must not be the value promoted over this basic equality of our votes.

This is why Score Voting (or Borda) in public governmental elections is wrong. If I enthusiastically prefer Candidate A and you prefer Candidate B only tepidly, your vote for Candidate B counts no less (nor more) than my vote for A. The effectiveness of one’s vote – how much their vote counts – must not be proportional to their degree of preference but be determined only by their franchise. A citizen with franchise must have a vote that counts equally as much as any other citizen with franchise. For any ranked ballot, this means that if Candidate A is ranked higher than Candidate B then that is a vote for A, if only candidates A and B are contending (such as in the RCV final round). It doesn’t matter how many levels A is ranked higher than B, it counts as exactly one vote for A.

This is sacrosanct. If our votes are not to be counted equally, then I want my vote to count more than yours. If this is objectionable to you, then can we agree that your vote and my vote must count equally?

Now, one of the ugly problems in the current RCV debate is that different elections, with different purposes and structure, a single one-size-fits-all approach is advocated to solve whatever the problem is that we want RCV to solve. Specifically:

1. Single-Winner elections. There is no proportionality to be had. It truly *is* winner-take-all. Then the *only* way to value our votes equally is to have the majority rule. If more voters mark their ballots preferring Candidate A over Candidate B than the number of voters marking their ballots to the contrary, then Candidate B should not be elected. If Candidate B *were* to be elected, that would mean that the fewer voters preferring Candidate B had cast votes that had greater value and counted more than those votes from the greater number of voters preferring Candidate A.

2. Multi-Winner elections. This is where valuing our votes equally translates to Proportional Voting. In a 3-seat district with 60% Democrats, 30% GOP, and 10% someone else (third party or independent), it would seem fair that 2 of the 3 seats were won by Democrat candidates and 1 of the 3 goes to a GOP candidate. It would seem unfair if the Democrats controlled all three seats in that district. But we know that Bottoms-Up or simplistic IRV doesn't always accomplish that. This is why systems with quotas, surplus votes, fractional votes like the Gregory Method (or variants) are better than Bottoms-Up. This is not yet a solved problem and we must be willing to adjust the system as we learn more about it.

3. Apportioning delegates to presidential candidates in the Presidential Primary. This is the latest little twist where IRV is offered as the one-size-fixes-all solution, but without a lot of thought going into it. As a consequence, a couple of states have acted on this, but they really don't understand what they're doing. We already know the correct mathematics for apportioning representation based on the numbers of those represented. That is the Method of Equal Proportions a.k.a. the Huntington-Hill method. Here, a Hare-like elimination of irrelevant candidates makes sense until every presidential candidate remaining has sufficient voter support in the primary to deserve at least one delegate. But then, the apportionment must be fair and value our votes equally. But I don't see FairVote or any RCV advocates worrying about that "little detail".

Expand full comment
Patti Crane's avatar

Thank you for educating frustrated American voters searching for a better system to end the current electoral doom loop. Question: Are you in agreement with Lee Drutman's recent New York Times explainer on how multi-member districts could help break the logjam?

Expand full comment

No posts